Why doesn't PartialOrd
require irreflexivity !(a < a)
over <
? AFAICT PartialOrd
does not actually express any kind of ordering relation for <
. For:
<
: we need PartialOrd
+ Irreflexivity
<=
: we need PartialOrd
+ Eq
since ==
must be reflexive.PartialOrd + Eq + Total
Is this an oversight? If not, we should document that PartialOrd
requires:
!(a < a)
as well. That would make PartialOrd
's <
denote a strict partial order on <
.
AFAICT this is actually what was intended, since all the discussions I can find online about PartialOrd
talk about floats, and floats are strictly partially ordered under <
, but not non-strictly partially ordered under <=
, which would fit our current model that floats don't implement Eq
.
Also, the docs of PartialOrd
do not say what le
(<=
) and ge
(>=
) actually mean. AFAICT they mean nothing for PartialOrd
in isolation. From reading the source the default implementation is a < b || a == b
, which would denote a non-strict total ordering over <=
when Eq
is implemented. But since Eq
is not required for PartialOrd
, I'd guess that those overriding these implementations are allowed to do something else as long as they don't implement Eq
. It is unclear to me what that "something else" might mean, but the docs should probably say something about this.
Also, I haven't been able to find any document explaining why things are the way they are, but the fact that PartialOrd
requires PartialEq
makes no sense to me, and it doesn't make much sense either that PartialOrd
exposes le
(<=
) and ge
(>=
) methods, since as mentioned above, without Eq
, le
and ge
do not express any meaningful ordering relation. It seems that these traits, like all other "operators" traits, mix operator overloading with mathematical semantics: in some cases they are used to express mathematical concepts, like a strict partial ordering relation under <
, and in some other cases they are used "to provide <= for floats". If anybody has any links to any discussions / documentation about why things are the way they are I'd like to read them, and maybe we should add rationale sections to the docs.
In the RFC thread for is_sorted
, @ExpHP mentioned that PartialOrd
probably also requires: (a < b)
if and only if (b > a)
(they called it "the 'notational' axiom").
Irreflexivity is implied by said notational axiom and the semantics of partial_cmp
. Simple proof: for irreflexivity to not be satisfied, !(a < a)
would have to be false for some a
. This means that for some a
, a < a
would have to be true. Using the notational axiom that means that a > a
would have to be true as well (I swapped the two a
s). But a < a
and a > a
cannot be true at the same time (this last fact is merely implied by the type Ordering
... but I guess it's worth putting it in the docs explicitly).
Thus, instead of adding the axiom of Irreflexivity to the docs, one could also add the notational axiom (which we probably want to add anyway).
The docs are also unclear or plain wrong in regards to the provided methods lt
, le
and friends. The docs say:
PartialOrd
only requires implementation of thepartial_cmp
method, with the others generated from default implementations.However it remains possible to implement the others separately for types which do not have a total order.
This implies that one has to manually implement lt
and friends to achieve a non-total ordering. This is false. In fact it's misleading because lt
and friends need to be implemented in a way that has the same behavior as the default implementation. Otherwise partial_cmp
would disagree with lt
and friends. The docs should explicitly disallow such disagreement between methods. (Since semantics of lt
and friends mustn't be changed, the only reason to provide a manual implementation is speed.)
@RalfJung mentioned on IRC:
so x <= y must be (x < y || x == y)
PartialEq is more explicit: "Any manual implementation of ne must respect the rule that eq is a strict inverse of ne; that is, !(a == b) if and only if a != b."
I think that sentence was just forgotten for PartialOrd
That is, the docs should state that ge
is equivalent to gt || eq
and le
is equivalent to lt || eq
and that any manual implementation must respect that.
(Since semantics of lt and friends mustn't be changed, the only reason to provide a manual implementation is speed.)
Agreed. This is stated explicitly for PartialEq, it seems it as forgotten here.
it doesn't make much sense either that PartialOrd exposes le (<=) and ge (>=) methods, since as mentioned above, without Eq, le and ge do not express any meaningful ordering relation.
I think that's the wrong way to think about it: PartialOrd is only a single operation, partial_cmp
. This operation is then used to define <, <=, > and >=. There is no choice left here, the only reason it is possible to override the default implementations (as @LukasKalbertodt said) is to make them go faster.
@ExpHP mentioned that PartialOrd probably also requires: (a < b) if and only if (b > a) (they called it "the 'notational' axiom").
Yeah that sounds pretty reasonable. I'd express this as "> is the dual to <", I think that's the common terminology in maths.
I briefly wondered how this relates to antisymmetry... but antisymmetry is a strange axiom in this context. In fact, antisymmetry is impossible to violate! If a < b
, then partial_cmp(a, b) == Some(Less)
, so we already have !(a > b)
. So, I think we can just drop it. If we require that lt
and gt
are defined in terms of partial_cmp
(or equivalent), antisymmetry will always hold.
(EDIT: This assume !(a < b)
is the negated boolean a < b
... because I cannot imagine any other reasonable interpretation.)
So, I think we can just drop it. I
Wouldn't we then need to require that if partial_cmp(a,b) == Some(Less)
then partial_cmp(b, a) == Some(Greater)
or something like that?
EDIT: I see this as just trading one axiom for another. We probably should document the axioms both in term of the comparisons <
, ==
, ... (which is more easy for some people to understand) and in terms of partial_cmp
(which is what everybody has to implement).
Wouldn't we then need to require that if partial_cmp(a,b) == Some(Less) then partial_cmp(b, a) == Some(Greater) or something like that?
That's the "notational" (or "duality") axiom: a < b
implies b > a
.
That's the "notational" (or "duality") axiom: a < b implies b > a.
Aha! Yeah if we add that axiom then we don't need anti-symmetry. Nice!
The wikipedia page on strict partial orders actually mentions this, that one axiom follows from the other two:
* not a < a (irreflexivity),
* if a < b and b < c then a < c (transitivity), and
* if a < b then not b < a (asymmetry; implied by irreflexivity and transitivity).
(just note that we don't require irreflexivity yet)
So to make a more concrete proposal. We currently have PartialOrd
specified as:
Trait for values that can be compared for a sort-order.
The comparison must satisfy, for all
a
,b
andc
:
- antisymmetry: if
a < b
then!(a > b)
, as well asa > b
implying!(a < b)
; and- transitivity:
a < b
andb < c
impliesa < c
. The same must hold for both==
and>
.Note that these requirements mean that the trait itself must be implemented symmetrically and transitively: if
T: PartialOrd<U>
andU: PartialOrd<V>
thenU: PartialOrd<T>
andT: PartialOrd<V>
.
Including all feedback above, we could change that to (strawman):
Strict partial ordering relation.
The comparison must satisfy, for all
a
,b
andc
:
- transitivity: if
a < b
andb < c
thena < c
- duality: if
a < b
thenb > a
that is, in terms of
partial_cmp
:
- transitivity: if
partial_cmp(a,b) == Some(Less)
andpartial_cmp(b, c) == Some(Less)
thenpartial_cmp(a,c) == Some(Less)
- duality: if
partial_cmp(a, b) == Some(Less)
thenpartial_cmp(b, a) == Some(Greater)
The semantics of
le
(<=
) andge
(>=
) are defined as:
le(a,b) == (a < b || a == b)
ge(a,b) == (a > b || a == b)
The
lt
,le
,gt
, andge
methods are implemented in terms ofpartial_cmp
according to these rules. The default implementations can be overridden for performance reasons, but manual implementations must satisfy the rules above.From these rules it follows that
PartialOrd
must be implemented symmetrically and transitively: ifT: PartialOrd<U>
andU: PartialOrd<V>
thenU: PartialOrd<T>
andT: PartialOrd<V>
.Stronger ordering relations:
partial_cmp
is a non-strict partial ordering relation ifT: PartialOrd + Eq
partial_cmp
is a total ordering relation ifT: Ord
Corollaries: follow from _transitivity_ of
<
and _duality_
_irreflexivity_ of
<
:!(a < a)
_transitivity_ of
>
_asymmetry_ of
<
: ifa < b
then!(b < a)
_antisymmetry_ of
<
: ifa < b
then!(a > b)
I am not sure if everything does indeed follow properly from duality
and transitivity
. Even if it does, this is a question that some might have, and even if this is all trivial to prove, I think we should have a "Proofs" section in the docs of PartialOrd
with the proofs. Do you think that such a section makes sense?
@gnzlbg Awesome, thank you! A few things though:
partial_cmp
is a non-strict partial ordering relation ifT: PartialOrd + Eq
Are you sure? I don't think transitivity ("a <= b
and b <= c
implies a <= c
") can be derived from the axioms. E.g. if a == b
and b < c
, then either a < c
or a
and c
could be uncomparable. I don't see how the current axioms prevent a
and c
from being uncomparable, but maybe I missed something.
Strict partial ordering relation.
I would change this to "Strict partial ordering relationS." as the trait adds <
and >
, two new strict partial ordering relations. Maybe even change it to "Strict partial ordering relations <
and >
."
Maybe we want to explicitly state that lt
and friends return false
if partial_cmp
returns None
. Or in general we might want to talk about what returning None
means. And maybe add the information implied by Ordering
: "At most one of a < b
, a == b
and a > b
is true."
transitivity of
>
is implied by symmetry of==
, transitivity of<
and==
, and duality of<
.
I don't think you only need duality and transitivity of <
here:
a > b โ b > c โ a > c | using duality to mirror all relations
โ b < a โ c < b โ c < a | just change the order of the AND operands
โ c < b โ b < a โ c < a | we're done as this is the transitivity of `<` axiom
- I would change this to "Strict partial ordering relationS." as the trait adds < and >, two new strict partial ordering relations. Maybe even change it to "Strict partial ordering relations < and >."
I was talking here about partial_cmp
, not <
and >
which "follow" from it. I don't know a better way to put it yet, but I wanted to emphasize that partial_cmp
is the "relation" that users have to implement. From there it follows that <
and >
are strict partial orders. I don't know, I find partial_cmp
a bit weird to think about.
Maybe we want to explicitly state that lt and friends return false if partial_cmp returns None
So when I wrote the axioms in term of partial_cmp
I wrote a < b == (partial_cmp(a,b) == Some(less))
. Maybe we should explicitly mention this:
a < b
is partial_cmp(a,b) == Some(Less)
a > b
is partial_cmp(a,b) == Some(Greater)
I don't think you only need duality and transitivity of < here:
Yes you are correct, I ninja edited the post.
("a <= b and b <= c implies a <= c") can be derived from the axioms. E.g. if a == b and b < c, then either a < c or a and c could be uncomparable.
Step by step: "if a == b
and b < c
implies a < c || a == c
" is equivalent to "a < c
implies a < c || a == c
which is equivalent to "a < c
implies a < c
or a < c
implies a == c
" which is "true or false" which is "true". Or what am I missing?
I don't see how the current axioms prevent a and c from being uncomparable, but maybe I missed something.
The only requirement of Eq
over PartialEq
is reflexivity: a == a
. So IIUC that requires a to be comparable with itself.
I was talking here about
partial_cmp
, not<
and>
which "follow" from it. I don't know a better way to put it yet, but I wanted to emphasize thatpartial_cmp
is the "relation" that users have to implement. From there it follows that<
and>
are strict partial orders. I don't know, I findpartial_cmp
a bit weird to think about.
Mhh, yes that's tricky :/
But as far as I understand it, partial_cmp
is not a relation in the mathematical sense. From the Wikipedia article it looks like a binary relation is just a subset of the cartesian product X ร Y of two sets. Basically meaning that a relation just says true
or false
for every pair of members of the two sets. partial_cmp
certainly says more than that.
In fact, I think that partial_cmp
defines exactly three (disjunct) relations (disjunct meaning that no two of those relations have a member in common). I mean yes, "relation" is also just an English word that would fit here from a non-math standpoint. But since the documentation mentions some exact math terms, I wouldn't use "relation" (which has an exact mathematical definition) in the non-mathematical sense.
Maybe the first paragraph of PartialOrd
docs should be targeted at the standard user who is not interested in axioms or exact mathematical terms. Maybe explain it in terms of "comparison"?
Types that can be compared to one another (defines the operators
<
,<=
,=>
and>
).
Maybe we should explicitly mention this:
I'd say so.
Step by step: "if
a == b
andb < c
impliesa < c || a == c
" is equivalent to "a < c
impliesa < c || a == c
" which is equivalent to "a < c
impliesa < c
ora < c
impliesa == c
" which is "true or false" which is "true". Or what am I missing?
I'm not sure about your first step: you say "a == b
and b < c
" is equivalent to "a < c
". I mean it intuitively makes sense but can that be derived from the axioms? As far as I can think it through, you can only show that:
a > c
is false: otherwise a == b โ b < c โ a > c
is true, which is equivalent to a == b โ a > c โ c > b
(duality and swapping two terms), which is equivalent to a == b โ a > b
(transitivity of >
), which is false
(disjunction of >
and ==
relation).a == c
is false: otherwise a == b โ b < c โ a == c
is true, which is equivalent to b == c โ b < c
, which is false
(again due to disjunction of <
and ==
)So we still have two possibilities: either a < c
(what we want to show) or a
and c
are not comparable. To show that a < c
is in fact implied, we'd have to show that a
and c
are necessarily comparable, right? And:
The only requirement of
Eq
overPartialEq
is reflexivity:a == a
. So IIUC that requires a to be comparable with itself.
This only requires everything to be comparable with itself, which doesn't help us because a
and c
are not the same element.
But again, maybe I'm missing something.
@gnzlbg nice first strawman! I overall like it. I think before stating any axioms, however, we should define <
, <=
, >
and >=
(or maybe just <
and >
) in terms of partial_cmp
. Otherwise the axioms don't actually mean anything. Moreover, we should spell out what it means to "agree" with PartialEq
, I guess we want an axiom like "partial_cmp(a, b) == Some(Equal)
if and only if (a == b)
"?
partial_cmp is a non-strict partial ordering relation
partial_cmp is a total ordering relation
As @LukasKalbertodt pointed out, these statements are not well-typed: partial_cmp
is not a relation (it does not have type fn(T, T) -> bool
). Please spell out which relation(s) you mean: <
, <=
, >
, >=
?
Corollaries: follow from transitivity of < and duality
I'd add "and from the definition of <
et al. in terms of the same partial_cmp
"
I'm not sure about your first step: you say "a == b and b < c" is equivalent to "a < c".
This is some kind of congruence statement: Essentially, we demand that a == b
implies partial_cmp(a, c) == partial_cmp(b, c)
, or similar (and also for replacing the second argument).
So maybe, instead of what I said above, the real meaning of "PartialCmp
agrees with PartialEq
" is
a1 == a2
and b1 == b2
imply partial_cmp(a1, b1) == partial_cmp(a2, b2)
, ANDpartial_cmp(a, b) == Some(Equal)
if and only if (a == b)
However, these may be too strong for irreflexive equalities? NaN
seems fine though (this mandates that partial_cmp(NaN, NaN) == None
, but that seems reasonable).
Can we derive one of these axioms from the other? Or find one nicer axiom that implies both of them?
So, I've only been half-following this. I'm afraid I'll really only just be adding to the noise; but here's how I feel inclined to look at it:
<=
alone. Is difficult to elaborate right now as I am on my phone, but I picture the directed graph formed by edges from a
to b
wherever a <= b
.<=
? I think that for PartialOrd, it's just ~associativity.~ i mean transitivity!Tagging with @rust-lang/lang; they need to make a call before we can write docs.
Seems reasonable. The docs in this comment seem plausible to me.
Would it make sense to use rfcbot to gather consensus asynchronously?
Is there a recommended way to put up a documment that we could quickly edit for this collaboratively?
It appears to me that after @LukasKalbertodt and @RalfJung comments we are 95 % there, we just need to finish it, and for that it might be better if we would just have something that's "uptodate" and that we can quickly eidt.
@gnzlbg I don't know if that's what you had in mind, but I created a HackMD document from your comment. Everyone can login via GitHub and edit. But it might be better to have a tiny repository where we submit the documentation as PR and we can leave line comments?
@LukasKalbertodt thanks! I worked a bit on it there and this is how it looks now (it would be cool if the tool could create diffs, so maybe a github repo would be better for something like this in the future):
PartialOrd
DocumentationStrict partial ordering relation.
This trait extends the partial equivalence relation
provided by PartialEq
(==
) with partial_cmp(a, b) -> Option<Ordering>
,
which is a trichotomy
of the ordering relation when its result is Some
:
a < b
then partial_cmp(a, b) == Some(Less)
a > b
then partial_cmp(a, b) == Some(Greater)
a == b
then partial_cmp(a, b) == Some(Equal)
and the absence of an ordering between a
and b
when partial_cmp(a, b) == None
.
Furthermore, this trait defines <=
as a < b || a == b
and
>=
as a > b || a == b
.
The comparisons must satisfy, for all a
, b
, and c
:
a < b
and b < c
then a < c
a < b
then b > a
The lt
(<
), le
(<=
), gt
(>
), and ge
(>=
) methods are
implemented in terms of partial_cmp
according to these rules.
The default implementations can be overridden for performance reasons,
but manual implementations must satisfy the rules above.
From these rules it follows that PartialOrd
must be implemented
symmetrically and transitively: if T: PartialOrd<U>
and U: PartialOrd<V>
then U: PartialOrd<T>
and T: PartialOrd<V>
.
The following corollaries follow from transitivity of <
, duality,
and from the definition of <
et al. in terms of
the same partial_cmp
:
<
: !(a < a)
>
: if a > b
and b > c
then a > c
<
: if a < b
then !(b < a)
<
: if a < b
then !(a > b)
Stronger ordering relations can be expressed
by using the Eq
and Ord
traits, where the
PartialOrd
methods provide:
T: PartialOrd + Eq
T: Ord
@gnzlbg
(it would be cool if the tool could create diffs, so maybe a github repo would be better for something like this in the future)
Yes, diffs and PR-comments would be nice. I created a temporary repository and submitted the current documentation as PR. I'd suggest we could discuss everything there. I already left a few comments on the PR.
I also gave you push access to the repo, so feel free to change things as you like.
(small note: <
is the "strict partial order", and <=
the "non-strict partial order" - but the latter also requires Eq
- mathematically, the "operators" are the orders, not {partial_,}cmp
)
@eddyb I added a comment with an alternative formulation here.
Looks like C++ went with something a bit more complex.
I'm not sure, but it almost seems like they have an Ord + PartialEq
combination?
@eddyb The latest paper is P0515r3. The most relevant section for this discussion is probably "Section 2: Design" which defines the following comparison categories as types:
weak_equality
strong_equality
is a weak_equality
partial_ordering
is a weak_equality
weak_ordering
is a partial_ordering
strong_equality
is a weak_ordering
and a strong_equality
The values of the equality categories are:
weak_equality
returns {equivalent, nonequivalent}
strong_equality
returns {equal, unequal}
which are converted to {equivalent, nonequivalent}
when converted to weak_equality
results.This is very similar to rust: interpret PartialEq::eq -> bool
returning true
as equivalent
and false
as nonequivalent
, and when Eq
is also implemented interpret these as equal
and unequal
respectively.
The orderings are also pretty similar:
partial_ordering
values are {less, equivalent, greater, unordered}
which can be implicitly converted to the weak_equality
values as {nonequivalent, equivalent, nonequivalent, nonequivalent}
weak_ordering
values are {less, equivalent, greater}
and implicitly convert to:weak_equality
values as {nonequivalent, equivalent, nonequivalent}
partial_ordering
values as {less, equivalent, greater}
strong_ordering
values are {less, equal, greater}
and implicitly convert to:weak_ordering
values as {less, equivalent, greater}
strong_equality
values as {unequal, equal, unequal}
weak_equality
values as {nonequivalent, equivalent, nonequivalent}
The paper is a bit light on math details; maybe some of this is covered in Stepanov's "From Mathematics to Generic Programming" or "Elements of Programming, worth checking this out.
Basically, the paper says that a type should implement _equality
if only a == b
should be provided, and only _ordering
if a < b
should also be provided. It also says that it should implement partial_
if values can be unordered, weak_
if a == b
does not imply f(a) == f(b)
, and strong_
if a == b
implies f(a) == f(b)
, where in both last cases "f
reads only comparison-salient state that is accessible using the public const
members".
The most interesting examples are:
float
s: implement multiple orderings. The default provided by operator<=>
is partial_order
because of NaN
, however a total ordering is available in an opt-in way via the named comparison functions. That is a < b
returns the partial order, but std::strong_order(a, b)
returns the IEEE total order. The system is flexible enough to support this. It is as if in Rust one could implement PartialOrd::partial_cmp
with different semantics than Ord::cmp
, and also choose whether the PartialOrd
or the Ord
implementations map to <
(I happen to think that one of Rust's std
lib biggest mistakes is mixing operator overloading with mathematical semantics; they are orthogonal concerns that don't mix well).
CaseInsensitvieString
implements weak_ordering
because a == b
does not imply f(a) == f(b)
Another related concern I have with how the current traits work is that there is no way to express that some PartialOrd
relations actually denote a total order. For example, given:
impl PartialOrd<Foo> for Bar { ... }
there is no way to implement Ord<Foo> for Bar
.
I am confused, of course you can implement Ord
...? Or do you mean because it requires Eq
?
@RalfJung I've filled an issue in the rfc repo: https://github.com/rust-lang/rfcs/issues/2511
Maybe the explanation there is more clear?
Yes, I understand now where you are coming from. Thanks.
Most helpful comment
In the RFC thread for
is_sorted
, @ExpHP mentioned thatPartialOrd
probably also requires:(a < b)
if and only if(b > a)
(they called it "the 'notational' axiom").Irreflexivity is implied by said notational axiom and the semantics of
partial_cmp
. Simple proof: for irreflexivity to not be satisfied,!(a < a)
would have to be false for somea
. This means that for somea
,a < a
would have to be true. Using the notational axiom that means thata > a
would have to be true as well (I swapped the twoa
s). Buta < a
anda > a
cannot be true at the same time (this last fact is merely implied by the typeOrdering
... but I guess it's worth putting it in the docs explicitly).Thus, instead of adding the axiom of Irreflexivity to the docs, one could also add the notational axiom (which we probably want to add anyway).
The docs are also unclear or plain wrong in regards to the provided methods
lt
,le
and friends. The docs say:This implies that one has to manually implement
lt
and friends to achieve a non-total ordering. This is false. In fact it's misleading becauselt
and friends need to be implemented in a way that has the same behavior as the default implementation. Otherwisepartial_cmp
would disagree withlt
and friends. The docs should explicitly disallow such disagreement between methods. (Since semantics oflt
and friends mustn't be changed, the only reason to provide a manual implementation is speed.)